Postmodernism is by definition a very plural worldview. There
is no clearly identifiable core per se. However, there are some recurring
themes which most of its adherents would tend to agree on. I think that the primary thrust of postmodernism is literary, social,
political and historical. It is not directed at sciences or their critique. This
took me a while to come to grips with. When I realized this, some confusion
went away.
Postmodernism has often been introduced briefly by borrowing
Lyotard’s statement – “postmodernism is the incredulity towards all
metanarratives.” Rightly so. If there is to be one one-sentence summary of
postmodernism, this would be it (for now.) What does it mean? In short, it
levels the field between all competing worldviews. At the same time, it also
declares all of them to be ‘untrue’ in some sense. This is a very nuanced point
and is often mistaken by naïve critiques of this statement.
The postmodern stance with regards to the earlier worldviews
is that they are epistemically partial at best and hollow at worst (not because
of any inherent issue but more so because of the very nature of human
epistemic apparatus). The worldviews/meta-narratives might contain grains of
factual ‘truth’ (using the convention of collective agreement and
reproducibility for empirical matters and collective sense of ‘logical’ for a
priori matters). Besides these, the worldviews routinely contain articles of
faith, belief, opinion, stand etc. The overall construct includes some ‘true’
facts, some ideas, some interpretations and so on. This collective is not
necessarily ‘wrong’ or ‘incorrect’ (in fact, postmodern stand is that such a
statement has no meaning.) However, competing worldviews are routinely calling
each other so (‘wrong’, ‘incorrect’, ‘inhuman’, ‘oppressive’, ‘cruel’ etc.)
Postmodernism enters this tournament and tells them that the prize is a hoax.
Let me go beyond the colorful analogy. Postmodernism does
not take a stand on right, wrong, just, correct and so on. It has a good reason
to do so, which we will come to later. However, in not taking a stand, it also
declares that the stands taken by everyone else are also arbitrary. This is not
a light charge on the stand-taking in the spirit of “I am not taking the stand because
I am confused and hence it is only fair that nobody else should take a stand too.” There is
more to it. That is what we come to now.
Postmodernism draws a lot on its critique of the role of
language in human life. While earlier worldviews took language as simply a tool
to express thoughts and ideas and rarely doubted its neutrality,
postmodernism got into the depth of this toolbox itself. The modern stance
regarding language is understandable. In fact, that continues to be the stand
taken by majority of humanity even now. Language is language. It has a
structure, words, grammar and so on. Someone uses it to construct stories,
someone else for poetry, yet someone else for a political speech and someone
writes erotic novels with it. It is malleable, universal and (while nobody
bothers to check it) impartial to all who use it. In fact, we rarely bother to
even stop and question this. It is too internal to us. It is a part of who we
are. Questioning language is like questioning our nose or liver.
And yet when any sensible person reviews the role played by
language in our discourses, it is hard to miss that language does not merely
clothe our thoughts, it builds them. Without language, there would be no
thoughts in the conventional sense that we experience them. If you do not
believe me, try it right now. Hold off reading, close your eyes and try to
think without language.
While we think we use language to ‘express’ or ‘articulate’
our thoughts, we always use language to ‘construct’ them. Even if that were
true, what of it? One might argue that language used for everyone on
collectively agreed principles to communicate thoughts. Where does the ‘incredulity
towards all metanarratives’ emerge from this?
Here, we need to take a slight detour to revisit Wittgenstein
– in his study of linguistics, the nature of logic and his eventual claim that
language simply cannot address some questions. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophical_Investigations)
Excerpt from Wikipedia entry: He
alleges that the problems are traceable to a set of related assumptions about
the nature of language, which themselves presuppose a particular conception of
the essence of language. This conception is considered and ultimately rejected
for being too general; that is, as an essentialist account of the nature of
language it is simply too narrow to be able to account for the variety of
things we do with language.
What this leads us to is a dead end of sorts. What are we to
do if someone asks us – ‘is it right to let one person die to save two?’
We get into ‘rational’ evaluation and get somewhere. We argue vociferously –
some would say it is the individual’s ‘right’, others would say it is ‘pragmatic’
to do this and so on. Ultimately, if it came to action, the actor would decide
based on a combination of factors, including some situational ones, some
unconscious ones and some ideological ones. What Wittgenstein claims is not
that this action is irrelevant but that the debate is. Our use of language to
address such questions is too ambitious. The structure of language is not equipped to deal with this.
Thus our thinking is unable to 'answer' these questions logically. What seems 'logical' is merely a product of some assumptions which are themselves questionable.
There is more. It is not that we are dumb or our language can
be ‘improved’. These questions are simply invalid. They are not in the realm of
thinking and evaluation. They simply belong to the domain of activity.
This is the fatal blow to the meta-narratives referred to
earlier in this essay. To the extent that a metanarrative has no such
statement barred by the Wittgensteinian inference above, it can at least claim
to be valid. However, it does not take much to realize that anything amounting
to a useful worldview is unlikely to be simple enough to be free from
opinion, faith, belief and ideology. Hence all substantial metanarratives are untrue. They are not 'incorrect', they are simply 'untrue'.
Postmodernism does not offer one more metanarrative to
replace these. It simply states that any such attempt it based on invalid
grounds.
There are three nuanced points here.
- 1 This incredulity is extended only to metanarratives. The smaller units of discourse such as a logical sentence and a fact of nature are dealt with differently. See below.
- 2. Most postmodern thought also includes a conjecture on why these metanarratives came to be in the first place and why they are so visible even when they are manufactured.
- 3. The critique of postmodernism on the ground that this itself is a metanarrative misses the point. There are multiple levels of organization of thought and each higher level can make claims about the lower levels.
1.
Naturalism is a metanarrative and so is feminism.
The statement that “2+2=4” or that “2 is the only even prime” are not.
Postmodernism is raising a question about the credulity of naturalism or feminism.
It is not questioning the validity of “2+2=4”. No doubt, it has an attitude towards the latter as well. That is interesting and somewhat liberating. What we consider
logical is based on our structure of language and conventions. In a slightly
different language of base 3 for example 2+2 = 11. Now if you know a little bit
of mathematics, you will say that 2 stands for two instances of something – say two
men. Addition stands for combing them while retaining their identities and
distinction. Hence when we say, two plus two, we are saying bring two men first
and then bring two more and start counting them. What they make as a result is
same – referred to as 4 in base 10 (actually in any base larger than base 5)
but 11 in base 3.
The postmodern response is not to refute the logic of these claims. It is
simply to point out that this is how we construct our language. This is how we
build our conventions of it – formal language like mathematics and logic or
informal language like English. All of these are systems of rules. Once we take
the rules as a given, the ‘truth’ of some claims and ‘falsity’ of some others
will follow.
Another example is empirical. In Euclidean geometry, angles of a triangle
add up to 180 degree (or two pi radians). For triangles drawn on the surface of
a sphere, they add up to more (anywhere between slightly more than 180 degrees
to say as high as nearly 540 degrees – think of a triangle with one point at
north pole, other two points near each other on equator and the line connecting
these nearby points being taken across the globe.) Again a matter of frame of
reference or the rulebook. Hence “2+2=4” (or for that matter “2+2=11”) is not
fundamentally or a priori ‘true’ as much as ‘internally consistent’ with the
rulebook of that particular sign system. Is this a big deal? Have I simply replaced
‘true’ with ‘internally consistent’?
It is a big deal, especially considering the veneration we accord to ‘the’
truth. In our fantasy, ‘the’ truth is independent, self-referential, profound
and all such. ‘Internally consistent’ is far shorter a claim. It is a claim
of observation. It has no profundity and more importantly no finality. Perhaps
the most important aspect of ‘internally consistent’ as against ‘true’ is that it
is not unique. There are many ways to construct an internally consistent
geometry for example. None of these are true or false. None are fundamentally
any better or worse than each other.
To summarize: postmodern claim about metanarratives is that they are not
credible. As regard analytical ‘truths’, postmodern stand is that they are products
of the language they are constructed in – and are thus ‘internally consistent’ instead
of the magnanimous ‘true’. As regard empirical truths, they are simply the
latest theory of how things work. (I have not elaborated on this last point,
but a quick review of Karl Popper’s falsification principle would explain this with
great lucidity.)
2.
At the beginning of this essay I made a claim
that the primary thrust of postmodernism is socio-political, historical and literary
rather than empirical. I had a reason to say so. Postmodernism arose in
reaction to the modern notion of how society should be organized, how new ideas
from scientific advances should inform our worldview and how we should view our
place in the universe. It is a critique of these human matters rather than any
philosophy of science.
Postmodernism came up as a reaction to what seemed like the use of
metanarratives for oppression and exploitation. To that extent, postmodernism -
for some its adherents - tends to have political under-currents. It seems to
prefer an anarchist society and tends to view worldviews and metanarratives as
ploys deployed by vested interests to their own ends.
I do agree with the critiques of postmodernism when they claim that
postmodernism seems to contradict itself in this sphere at times by taking a political
stand. A true postmodern attitude to politics is in fact absence of a
recommendation regarding opinion. Hence any opinion could be admitted insofar
as it did not have overarching claims regarding where its legitimacy came from.
But therein lies the rub. While fighting the general proliferation of
competing metanarratives, it is hard to push through a view of incredulity towards
metanarratives without taking a stand. While I referred earlier in an analogy
to the tournament where postmodernism enters to declare the prize to be a hoax,
in real social discourse, one gets heard only when one has something to say.
The construct of language does not allow a well defined postmodern rhetoric to
flourish in the current social set up, at least.
Nevertheless, for those that sense what the spirit of postmodernism is,
its political implications are simple enough. Postmodernism may not stand a
good chance in a social fight outside of the individual. However, within a
given individual, it can warn her that all metanarratives are power-plays. The subtlety,
(because of which it would fail to gather followers in a popular sense), is
that postmodernism has no recommendation regarding how to form your own
worldview. In fact, this might be its Achilles’ heel. For a budding
intellectual, postmodernism is sterile. If I seriously follow the thought of
following no metanarrative, I suddenly find myself unhinged. The postmodern
response to it is vague. Different adherents have said different things.
Foucault for example says that maximizing one’s own pleasure is a good guiding
principle. That seems too narrow to begin with – although that is where a thoughtful
journey might end. It also fails to inspire – something that a serious
worldview has to do in the context of current cultural and social set-up. A
worldview as sterile as postmodernism then is starting out with a huge
handicap. But I digress. Coming back to the main point of its political
recommendation, postmodernism can be seen as the liberating first step. The
second step is then to find out what you would like to use this liberation for.
3.
Some critiques point out that ‘all metanarratives
are invalid’ is itself a metanarrative and hence self-contradictory. I would
argue that it is not. Firstly I have explained earlier that a metanarrative is
different from a statement of logic or empirical finding. Some would say that ‘all
metanarratives are invalid’ is a pretty strong ideological stance and has a
fair amount of belief in it and this could qualify to be a metanarrative itself.
This is partly true. Hence I am adding a qualifier to Lyotard’s statement.
‘Postmodernism is incredulity towards all first-level metanarratives.’ Is this
simply a language-game, where I raise this statement to the second level
metanarrative state and thus claim it to be valid? It might seem so but it is
not.
Any system of signs does not operate at a single level. For example, when
I claim the validity of “2+3=5”, I am using the higher (or lower, whichever,
but different) level assumption about what 2,3,+ and = mean. Once this higher
level assumption is considered valid, I can gauge validity or invalidity of
2+3=5 and 2+3=7. Without the higher level assumptions or system, the lower
level statement cannot be evaluated. A simple demonstration is trying to read a
language you don’t know. The symbols don’t mean anything. You don’t have the
higher level assumptions.
As regards statements about metanarratives and worldviews are concerned,
one can similarly see the relevance of such a higher level system. I would say
the following statements are all competing approaches to worldviews/metanarratives (merely an illustration.)
a.
There is exactly one correct metanarrative/worldview.
All other worldviews are false.
b.
All worldviews and metanarratives are correct.
In their given context, they serve the useful purpose of helping an individual
live with the vagaries of life.
c.
All metanarratives are invalid. They are
constructed using the language to serve specific purposes of their users.
These are all higher level statements about metanarratives. Say, the
first one does not implicitly mean that it itself is that one correct
metanarrative. Similarly the third one does not become invalid as a
metanarrative in itself.
Seen from the other side, i.e. the contents of the typical metanarratives, this
becomes even clearer. Most metanarratives are systems that assume some things,
repose faith in some others and follow some ideological stance. These particulars
are ‘real’ – in the sense that they deal with human lives. At a core level, a
typical metanarrative at the first level does not bother to make too much of a
statement about the nature of metanarratives, language and its limitations and
so on. Of course, it might contradict another first level metanarrative (e.g.
Theism vs Naturalism). But it does not aspire to make too many claims about epistemology
and construction of worldviews in the first place. In short, a typical first
level metanarrative is generally not self-referential. In fact that is the appeal
of most of these. They are seductive for precisely that reason. By avoiding any
reference to self, they remain clear of any criticism by followers. A faithful
follower of some of the popular first level metanarrative would rarely come
across a contradiction in it. These systems tend to be internally
self-consistent. (There might be others that did not manage that and thus
perished – sort of survival of the fittest logic for ideas!) In precisely this
characteristic of these systems lies the means of exploitation. When the Jihdist
is sent on a suicide mission, he believes that he is going to meet virgins to
copulate after death (not all for sure, many simply do it for the money their
families receive.) The constructors of their metanarrative exploit this
unquestioning faith. Much less visible and less extreme examples abound in our
daily lives. More on that later though.
In
summary: first level metanarratives generally serve specific purpose of providing
individuals and societies with internally consistent rulebook of living. Second
level metanarratives are not very common nor popular. Postmodernism, even if considered
as a metanarrative, is a second level metanarrative and is thus not
self-contradictory.
1 comment:
Post a Comment